Charles R. Twardy

Follow @ctwardy on Micro.blog.

What is a replication

In a recent Nature essay urging pre-registering replications, Brian Nosek and Tim Errington note:

Conducting a replication demands a theoretical commitment to the features that matter.

That draws on their paper What is a replication? and Nosek’s earlier UQ talk of the same name arguing that a replication is a test with “no prior reason to expect a different outcome.”

Importantly, it’s not about procedure. I wish I’d thought of that, because it’s obvious after it’s pointed out. Unless you are offering a case study, you should want your result to replicate when there are differences in procedure.

But psychology is a complex domain with weak theory. It’s hard to know what will matter. There is no prior expectation that the well-established Weber-Fechner law would fail among the Kalahri – but it would be interesting if it did. The well-established Müller-Lyer illusion does seem to fade in some cultures. That requires different explanations.

Back to the Nature essay:

What, then, constitutes a theoretical commitment? Here’s an idea from economists: a theoretical commitment is something you’re willing to bet on. If researchers are willing to bet on a replication with wide variation in experimental details, that indicates their confidence that a phenomenon is generalizable and robust. … If they cannot suggest any design that they would bet on, perhaps they don’t even believe that the original finding is replicable.

This has the added virtue of encouraging dialogue with the original authors rather than drive-by refutations. And by pre-registering, you both declare that before you saw the results, this seemed a reasonable test. Perhaps that will help you revise beliefs given the results, and suggest productive new tests.